Skip to main content

Why charities need stricter rules on fundraising

A government commissioned review is currently looking into the way UK charities raise money. Reports this week suggest it will be tough. And it should be! The review follows the high profile case of 92 year old Olive Cooke who took her own life having become exhausted by requests for money from charities. Such requests for money are all too familiar to many. In our household I would say that we average a charity letter per day, a phone call per week, and a fundraiser at the door every month. The Prime Minister was stating the obvious when he said that the behaviour of some charities was 'frankly unacceptable'.
          Against this public backlash the charity sector has stood firm. Time and again I have heard spokespeople arguing that charities only do good. The argument essentially seems to be that the funds they raise are spent on worthy causes and so the ends justify the means. The charity sector, therefore, can claim the moral high ground. This argument, however, is flawed.
          Charities provide public goods. It is textbook economics that public goods will be under-provided. This means that voluntary donations to charity will not be enough to provide an efficient amount of the public good - children will go hungry, old people will be lonely, and so on. In order to obtain an efficient amount a public good some form of coercion seems necessary. That's why we don't have any choice to pay taxes. And this is why charities could argue that the ends justify the means. Even if their fundraising tactics do include a heavy dose of coercion, so what - society is better off as a result.
          The flaw in this argument is one of asymmetry. We all have to pay taxes. Not all of us are targeted by charities. We know from lab experiments that approximately 50% of people can be classified as free-riders and 50% as conditional co-operators. Free-riders will not voluntarily give to charity. Conditional co-operators will. Who do charities go after? It is, of course, the conditional co-operators. The more a person gives to charity the more they are asked to give. So, conditional co-operators are coerced into giving more while free-riders get off scot-free. Where is the moral high ground in this? It seems neither fair nor just.
           It is also likely to backfire. That's because of the conditional in conditional co-operator. A conditional co-operator will give only if they feel they are not being exploited. And the recent behaviour of charities may well make them feel as though they are being exploited. Charities could well, therefore, see cracks appearing in their core support.
          The charity sector has over-stepped the mark. It would be nice to think that they could fix the problem themselves. If they do start to see cracks in their core support then they may. More realistically, however, we are going to need legislation. Otherwise we will end up with even more children going hungry and old people lonely.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. Divide 40 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass ______ at $3 each. In this case each token given to th

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In other words Adam and Beth should be able to gain from agreeing.

Some estimates of price elasticity of demand

In the  textbook on Microeconomics and Behaviour with Bob Frank we have some tables giving examples of price, income and cross-price elasticities of demand. Given that most of the references are from the 70's I'm working on an update for the forthcoming 3rd edition. So, here is a brief overview of where the numbers come from for the table on price elasticity of demand. Suggestions for other good sources much appreciated. Before we get into the numbers - the disclaimer. Price elasticities are tricky things to tie down. Suppose you want the price elasticity of demand for cars. This elasticity is likely to be different for rich or poor people, people living in the city or the countryside, people in France or Germany etc.etc. You then have to think if you want the elasticity for buying a car or using a car (which includes petrol, insurance and so on). So, there is no such thing as the price elasticity of demand for cars. Moreover, the estimated price elasticity will depend o