Skip to main content

Running with the Kenyans and human capital formation

Over christmas I had chance to read the book Running with The Kenyans by Adharanand Finn. In short the book is about a British guy's experience of immersing himself for six months in the Kenyan running culture. A recurring theme throughout the book is the question of why Kenyan's have come to dominate long distance running. The answer clearly depends on a number of things like high altitude, running to school etc. But the main thing seems to be a culture of running. Kenyans run because that is what Kenyans do. So, what has that got to do with economics?
       There can be no doubt that Kenyan athletes take running very seriously. In other words they put in hours and hours of training (and perhaps more importantly put in hours and hours of dedicated rest). An economist would think of this as human capital formation. All the hours of dedication to running are about the person improving their ability to run fast so that he or she can eventually win some races and make some money and get some reward. It is a person's investment in future productivity. Very few Kenyan athletes go on, however, to win races and make money. For most the investment in running does not pay off in terms of increased productivity. Currrent economic theory is very poorly placed to explain outcomes like this. 
       The textbook model of human capital formation primarily focuses on how much to invest in human capital formation. Implicit in this seems to be an assumption of 'linearity' from less well educated and less productive to well educated and more productive. For example, years of schooling and achievements at school or university are seen as good measures of productivity. Reality is, however, far more multi-dimensional that this. Put another way, human capital is not always very transferable. For example, a Kenyan who has spent years training to be a runner is not going to do well as an economics professor. And a Brit who has spent years doing economics is not going to win many marathons. Someone investing in human capital not only, therefore, has to decide how much to invest they also have to decide what to invest in. Should they train to be a runner, economist, physicist, pianist, actor, writer, .....
       Once we recognize the multi-dimensional nature of human capital we realize the matching problem inherent in labour supply. Society is only willing to support so many Kenyan athletes, or concert pianists, or economists. Inefficiency in solving this matching problem is why most Kenyans, despite being faster than the best British athletes, do not make it as professional runners. And reasons we end up with such inefficiencies are not hard to find. Most crucially, human capital formation takes a long time and is basically irreversible. People cannot, therefore, learn from experience. And how is a teenager supposed to know where best their future lies? Things are made even more complicated by the winner-take-all nature of many of the professions that require high human capital. Because only a handful of athletes make serious money the law of large numbers 'smoothing' effect does not come into play. This results in a big drop between being good enough and being not quite good enough. Again, how can a teenager know they are going to be good enough? Do not expect good choices.
        I got interested in the matching nature of the labour market in the early days of my PhD (with one paper to show for it). At that stage I felt a frustration at how poorly the matching within the labour market were understood. From what I can tell, not much has come along to improve our understanding. So, why are economists not studying this more? I would suggest an unwillingness to accept the basic ad-hoc nature of the labour market is the main issue. If I look back at my life: there was no grand plan to be an economist or invest in specific types of human capital; there were though lots of events that could have easily been different, and if they had been different I would not have been an economist. Most people surely stumble through life in a similar way. Acknowledging this is a big step from the standard economic models of utility maximization. But it can help explain why Kenyans go out running despite little chance of winning the New York Marathon. It can also help us better understand unemployment, skills gaps, and income inequality.
           
         

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. Divide 40 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass ______ at $3 each. In this case each token given to th

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In other words Adam and Beth should be able to gain from agreeing.

Some estimates of price elasticity of demand

In the  textbook on Microeconomics and Behaviour with Bob Frank we have some tables giving examples of price, income and cross-price elasticities of demand. Given that most of the references are from the 70's I'm working on an update for the forthcoming 3rd edition. So, here is a brief overview of where the numbers come from for the table on price elasticity of demand. Suggestions for other good sources much appreciated. Before we get into the numbers - the disclaimer. Price elasticities are tricky things to tie down. Suppose you want the price elasticity of demand for cars. This elasticity is likely to be different for rich or poor people, people living in the city or the countryside, people in France or Germany etc.etc. You then have to think if you want the elasticity for buying a car or using a car (which includes petrol, insurance and so on). So, there is no such thing as the price elasticity of demand for cars. Moreover, the estimated price elasticity will depend o