Skip to main content

Obesity and nudging over the long term

A recent issue of Nature had a special report on obesity. One of the articles looked at the merits of  behavioural interventions in tackling obesity and came to a somewhat pessimistic conclusion. In particular, the article pointed to evidence that behavioural interventions produce only short term gains - weight loss over the first 6 to 12 months but creeping weight gain thereafter. This is bad news for anyone wanting to tackle obesity. It also raises questions about the general benefits of behavioural interventions.
        And this second point is especially interesting given that behaviour change is very much a buzz idea at the moment. Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein have done most to publicize the idea with their book Nudge, but they are by no means the only advocates. The popularity of behaviour change stems largely from its seeming simplicity and cost effectiveness: people's decisions are effected by the way choices are framed and so framing choices in a particular way change change behaviour in predictable and desirable ways. 
         The nudges that have received most attention are those explicitly related to financial decisions like saving for retirement, paying tax returns etc. But, eating also seems an area apt for a bit of nudge. For example, smaller plates might mean you eat less, the positioning of food in the canteen buffet might mean you make healthier choices, keeping a food diary may mean you eat less and make healthier choices, a pedometer app might mean you walk more, and publicizing your exercise or weight loss plans to friends and family might make you more likely to stick to plan.
        The continuing interest in behaviour change is evidence that it has delivered results. Nudges have proved successful in increasing saving, reducing tax evasion and so on. But, what if the gains are only short term, as the experience in tackling obesity suggests? Clearly this sounds like bad news for advocates of behaviour change. To me, it suggests two important caveats that need to be kept in mind when thinking through the consequences of behaviour change:
        1. Some decisions we make very infrequently, such as how much to save for retirement. Some decisions we make very frequently, such as what to have for dinner. 'Short term' can, thus, mean widely different things depending on the context. Nudges can have 'long lasting' success if decisions are made infrequently; if, for example, you change your retirement saving plan then you may be set for life. But, nudges may wear off quickly if decisions are made frequently; if, for example, you buy some smaller plates you may eat less for a month or two but soon be back to normal.
       So, why do the effects of nudges wear off? Nudges work by changing framing and that works because of the heuristics we use. If, for example, you use a heuristic 'fill my plate one cm high with food' then buying some smaller plates means less food. This, though, need not change your underlying preferences. So, after a few months of feeling hungry you likely adapt your heuristic to, say, 'fill my plate two cm high with food'. (Note that this means you then end up eating more when you go to the self service canteen!) Such adaption suggests that, in a context where decisions are made frequently, nudges may not be enough. A more fundamental 'change in preferences' is required.
        2. But how do we 'change preferences'? Preferences are largely determined by culture, norms and the like. So, changing the behaviour of one person is a drop in ocean. Instead, it may be that society as a whole needs a nudge in the right direction. And that likely requires some big policy intervention.
        The article on obesity, with which I began, concludes: 'Ultimately, the only effective, sustainable solution - on a large scale over the long term - may be to change the culture. "The issue to me is not whether or not behavioral interventions work," Katz [director of the Yale-Griffin Prevention Research Center] says. "There's absolutely no question to me that they are the thing we have to depend on." But even the most comprehensive programme, he says, is no match for a culture built around calorie-dense foods and sedentary lifestyles. "Behavioural interventions are a very slow march forward on a walkway that's going in reverse".

        

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. D...

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In...

Prisoners dilemma or stag hunt

Over Christmas I had chance to read The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure by Brian Skyrms. A nice read, very interesting and thought provoking. There’s a couple of things in the book that prompt further discussion. The one I want to focus on in this post is the distinction between the stag hunt game and the prisoners dilemma game.    To be sure what we are talking about, here is a specific version of both type of game. Adam and Eve independently need to decide whether to cooperate or defect. The payoff matrix details their payoff for any combination of choices, where the first number is the payoff of Adam and the second number the payoff of Eve. For example, in the Prisoners Dilemma, if Adam cooperates and Eve defects then Adam gets 65 and Eve gets 165. Prisoners Dilemma Eve Cooperate Defect Adam Cooperate 140, 140 65, 165 Defect 165,...