Skip to main content

Is it easier to provide a threshold public good if potential contributors are poor?

A threshold (or step-level) public good is a good that would benefit members of a group but can only be provided if there are sufficient contributions to cover the cost of the good. A local community raising funds for a new community centre is one example. Flatmates trying to get together enough money to buy a new TV is another.
         There are some fundamental strategic parameters in any threshold public good game: number of group members (n), the threshold amount of money needed (T), the value of the good if provided (V), and the endowment of money that group members have available to contribute (E). Early experimental studies looked at the role of n, T and V but had little to say about E. This raised the intriguing question of whether E matters. Is it 'easier' to provide a threshold public good if group members are relatively rich or poor?
         To find out we needed to run some experiments. In two recently published papers, with Federica Alberti and Anna Stepanova, we report our findings. In this blog entry I will talk about a study with Federica Alberti published in Finanz Archiv. This study is distinguished by the fact we looked at games with a refund or money-back guarantee if contributions fall short of the threshold.
         The benchmark game in the experimental literature has n = 5, T = 125, V = 50 and E = 55. This means that if group members split the cost of providing the public good they would each have 55 - 125/5 = 30 left. Call this the endowment remainder. We compared this benchmark to games where, everything else the same, E = 30 and E = 70. This results in an endowment remainder of 5 and 45. You can think of these as games where group members are poor and rich, respectively. We also looked at two further games where the endowment remainder was 5 and 45 but T and V varied. This allowed us to check that our results are robust.  
          The figure below summarizes our overall results. You can see that there is some weak evidence of a lower success rate for the intermediate level of endowment. The differences, though, are hardly large. So, does the endowment make any difference? We claim it does.
 
 
         To see why, first note that successfully providing the public good requires coordination amongst group members. They want to contribute just enough to pay for the good. If group members  are relatively poor then it should be simple to coordinate because the good is only provided if all of them contribute most of their endowment - so there is nothing to disagree about. If group members are relatively rich then it should also be simple to coordinate because they have lots of money to spare - it is not worth disagreeing. The intermediate case may be more tricky.
          If this conjecture is correct we would expect groups to learn to coordinate when the endowment remainder is small or large. Our subjects played the game 25 times and so we can check for this. The next figure summarizes what happened in the last five plays of the game. As we would expect the success rate is now significantly higher with a low or high endowment.
 
 
          Another way to check our conjecture is to look at the variance in contributions around the threshold. The better group members are at coordinating, the lower should be the variance. The next figure summarizes the variance of contributions in the last five plays of the game. Here there is a big difference.  
 
 
         Our results, therefore, suggest that it is 'easier' for groups to provide the public good when group members are relatively poor or rich. The important caveat is that there should be sufficient time to learn how to coordinate. For an intermediate endowment group members seemingly could not coordinate no matter how much time they had. So, the endowment does matter.
          To turn this into practical guidance for fundraisers would suggest donors need to feel either critical - the poor case - or that giving will not cost them much - the rich case. It would be dangerous to enter the intermediate territory where, say, the donor is led to believe that the good could be provided without them - they are not critical - and that there donation would involve personal sacrifice - they are not rich.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. D...

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In...

Prisoners dilemma or stag hunt

Over Christmas I had chance to read The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure by Brian Skyrms. A nice read, very interesting and thought provoking. There’s a couple of things in the book that prompt further discussion. The one I want to focus on in this post is the distinction between the stag hunt game and the prisoners dilemma game.    To be sure what we are talking about, here is a specific version of both type of game. Adam and Eve independently need to decide whether to cooperate or defect. The payoff matrix details their payoff for any combination of choices, where the first number is the payoff of Adam and the second number the payoff of Eve. For example, in the Prisoners Dilemma, if Adam cooperates and Eve defects then Adam gets 65 and Eve gets 165. Prisoners Dilemma Eve Cooperate Defect Adam Cooperate 140, 140 65, 165 Defect 165,...