Skip to main content

Have you heard of Berge equilibrium? And should you have?

Recently I refereed a paper on the existence of Berge equilibrium. I must confess that until reading the paper I knew nothing of Berge equilibrium. But in my defence, the equilibrium does not get a mention in any game theory textbook on my shelves and, surely most telling of all, does not get an entry in Wikipedia. So, what is Berge equilibrium and should we hear more about it?

The origins of the equilibrium are a book by French mathematician Claude Berge (who does get a Wikipedia page) on a general theory of n-person games, first published in 1957. But it has seemingly gone pretty much unnoticed from then on, although there is a growing literature on the topic as summarized in a 2017 paper by Larbani and Zhukovskii. The basic idea behind Berge equilibrium seems to be one of altruism or cooperation between players in a group.

To explain, consider a game. Let si denote the strategy of player i, s-i the strategies of everyone other than i and ui(si, s-i) the payoff of player i given these strategies.

Nash equilibrium says that player i maximizes his or her payoff given the strategies of others. So, at a strict Nash equilibrium si*, s-i* we have

                                ui(si*, s-i*) > ui(si, s-i*) 

for all i and any other strategy si. This says that player i cannot do better by deviating.

Berge equilibrium says that each player maximizes the payoff of player i given his or her strategy. So, at a strict Berge equilibrium si*, s-i* we have

                                ui(si*, s-i*) > ui(si*, s-i

for all i and for any other strategy s-i. So, the other players do their best to maximize the payoff of player i.

The differences between Nash equilibrium and Berge equilibrium are easy illustrated in the prisoners dilemma. In the game depicted below Fred and William simultaneously have to decide whether to deny or confess. Nash equilibrium says that Fred should Confess because this maximizes his payoff (whatever William does). Berge equilibrium, by contrast, says that Fred should Deny because this maximizes the payoff of William.


Many have argued that Deny is the 'rational' choice in the prisoners dilemma (because both Deny is better than both Confess) and Berge equilibrium appears to capture that idea. Modern game theory, however, provides lots of ways to capture altruism or morality that are arguably more appealing. In particular we can add social preferences into the mix so that if Fred wants to help William then we put that into his payoff function. Then the prisoners dilemma (in material payoffs) is no longer a prisoners dilemma (in social preferences) because Fred maximizes his own payoff by Denying and helping William.

Berge equilibrium only makes sense if everyone is willing to fully sacrifice for others, and that seems a long shot. Unless, that is, players have some connections beyond that usually imagined in non-cooperative game theory. In other words Berge equilibrium may have some bite if we move towards the world of cooperative game theory where Fred and William are part of some coalition. We could, for instance, imagine Fred and William being brothers, part of a criminal gang or players on the same sport team. Here it starts to become more plausible to see full sacrifice. And that it brings us to the concept of team reasoning.

The basic idea behind team reasoning is that players think what is best for us. They act as a cohesive unit, like a family making choices. This looks similar to Berge equilibrium but is actually different. To see the difference consider the coordination game below. For both William and Fred to Cheat is a Berge equillibrium - given that Fred is going to cheat the best thing that William can do for Fred is also to cheat. But mutual Cooperation is clearly better (and also a Berge equilibrium). Team reasoning says unambiguously that both should Cooperate. So, team reasoning is arguably better at picking up sacrifice for the group cause.


Given the tools we have to model social preferences and team reasoning I am skeptical Berge equilibrium will ever get beyond the level of an historical curiosity. But it is still interesting to know that such a concept exists.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. Divide 40 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass ______ at $3 each. In this case each token given to th

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In other words Adam and Beth should be able to gain from agreeing.

Some estimates of price elasticity of demand

In the  textbook on Microeconomics and Behaviour with Bob Frank we have some tables giving examples of price, income and cross-price elasticities of demand. Given that most of the references are from the 70's I'm working on an update for the forthcoming 3rd edition. So, here is a brief overview of where the numbers come from for the table on price elasticity of demand. Suggestions for other good sources much appreciated. Before we get into the numbers - the disclaimer. Price elasticities are tricky things to tie down. Suppose you want the price elasticity of demand for cars. This elasticity is likely to be different for rich or poor people, people living in the city or the countryside, people in France or Germany etc.etc. You then have to think if you want the elasticity for buying a car or using a car (which includes petrol, insurance and so on). So, there is no such thing as the price elasticity of demand for cars. Moreover, the estimated price elasticity will depend o