Skip to main content

Pregnancy, smoking, and principal agent problems

Earlier this week it the headlines that NICE (the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence) were recommending midwives use a carbon monoxide test to verify whether expectant mothers were smoking. Suitable fury from smokers followed. The proposal, however, is based on pretty sound economics.
    The relationship between a child and parent is a principal-agent relationship. The basic idea of any such relationship is that a principal 'employs' an agent to do a 'job' for her. Its fine to interpret 'employs' and 'job' very loosely. In this case we can think of the unborn child as employing the mother to protect her growth and development. Clearly it is in the best interests of the child that the mother quit smoking, eat healthily etc. The mother, however, has different incentives. And, there were lots of mothers I heard on the radio this week determined to carry on smoking regardless. This is an example of a moral hazard problem: The agent, in this case the expectant mother, takes on more risk than the principal, the unborn child, would like her too.
    Many people, at least many of the students I have taught, like to argue that the parent child relationship shouldn't be see as an example of a principal agent problem. Surely the mother acts in the best interests of her child? While, it would be nice to think so, the reality is often very different - count how many pregnant women smoke. So, moral hazard exists. And that's not the only problem.
     People can choose when and whether to have children. If quitting smoking is difficult, then a responsible smoker would quit before getting pregnant. Some people do quit smoking before getting pregnant but others do not. Simple logic says that the people who get pregnant irrespective are going to have more children than those who wait until 'everything is right'. The adage that you cannot choose your parents, therefore, understates the true problem. You are more likely to be born to an irresponsible parent than a responsible parent! This is an example of an adverse selection problem: Less desirable agents are more likely to be employed. Or in this case, unborn children and relatively likely to end up with irresponsible parents.
     We cannot, therefore, trust pregnant mothers (and fathers) to stop smoking. And a further thing to keep in mind is that the pregnant mother is employed by the taxpayer as well as the child. This is because the National Health Service will pick up the bill if anything goes wrong. That lessens the incentive for mothers to act responsibly. Indeed, one could argue that the benefits system positively encourages irresponsible behavior. So, I have no hesitation in saying that the carbon monoxide test is a good idea. The test, however, does not solve the problem of what to do with expectant mothers that want to continue smoking. For that the Health Service needs a credible threat to encourage non-smoking - and its hard to think how to do that.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. D...

Measuring risk aversion the Holt and Laury way

Attitudes to risk are a key ingredient in most economic decision making. It is vital, therefore, that we have some understanding of the distribution of risk preferences in the population. And ideally we need a simple way of eliciting risk preferences that can be used in the lab or field. Charles Holt and Susan Laury set out one way of doing in this in their 2002 paper ' Risk aversion and incentive effects '. While plenty of other ways of measuring risk aversion have been devised over the years I think it is safe to say that the Holt and Laury approach is the most commonly used (as the near 4000 citations to their paper testifies).           The basic approach taken by Holt and Laury is to offer an individual 10 choices like those in the table below. For each of the 10 choices the individual has to go for option A or option B. Most people go for option A in choice 1. And everyone should go for option B in choice 10. At some point, therefore, we expect the...

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In...