Skip to main content

Add-on insurance and default options

One of the most basic and intuitive ideas that has come out of the behavioural change literature is the opt-in versus opt-out distinction. Essentially, because of psychological bias, people are likely to end up 'choosing' the default option. So if, for example, the default option is to not be opted into a pension savings plan a person is likely to end up not saving enough for retirement. This simple observation partly motivated the save more tomorrow plan that stands to revolutionise retirement saving.
        A context where default options are often used strategically is check boxes on online (or hard copy) forms. Suppose, for example, you want to travel from London to Birmingham and go to book your ticket online. If you are going by train then once you've sorted out the times of the trains etc. you will be offered the chance to buy basic travel insurance. In this case the box is not ticked and so the default option is no travel insurance - you have to click a mouse button to get insurance. If you are going by coach, by contrast, the box is ticked and so the default option is travel insurance - you have to click a mouse button to remove the insurance. The Financial Conduct Authority is concerned that such default opt-in options are essentially a form of miss-selling and so should be banned.
         To the standard economic model this all seems a little crazy. There is seemingly no-cost at all in clicking a mouse button to switch from opt-in to opt-out. And travel insurance is a product that some people might want to buy. So, why should we be banning default opt-in options? Should we not put the onus on consumers to make sensible decisions?
         To get some insight on these questions I think we need to take a step back and ask why default options matter. The standard reason given for why defaults matter is procrastination. A person, for instance, puts off changing their pension plans, until tomorrow, and then the day after, and then the day after that. Before long they have retired without the savings they hoped they would have. But, while this can explain the success of the save more tomorrow plan it says nothing about online check boxes. In the latter case the form is being filled here and now and so the decision simply cannot be left until tomorrow.
          We need, therefore, to question why defaults can matter beyond procrastination. I'll point to two reasons. First, we have a psychology bias to 'trust the seller knows what we want'. We naively think that the default option must be the right option - why else would it be the default. A little thought shows that this logic is really naïve - the seller wants to make as much profit as possible. But, we still fall for the trap. And things get worse when we take into account a second factor, namely that of anticipated regret. By unchecking the box to buy default travel insurance you set yourself up to feel regret if the insurance would subsequently have been useful. The fear of that regret may bias you towards sticking with the insurance. This is a variant of the endowment effect - you value something more when you feel you already own it. Observe how ridiculous this can end up being: When you sat down to buy the tickets you had no thoughts about travel insurance. But once the 'seed is in your head' and you have to 'consciously do something' to opt-out, travel insurance suddenly seems an essential!
          Seen in this light, I think the Authority is right to get involved and ban default opt-ins. They are essentially a way of 'fooling' the customer into feeling they need something they do not. To say that consumers have the choice to opt-out is not really the point. Consumers are forced to consciously opt-out of something and pay the psychological cost for doing that. Indeed, notice that everyone suffers - some buy something they do not need, while others pay (a small) psychological cost of 'giving something up'. If travel insurance is worth buying the onus should be on the company to prove its worth buying. 
           
         

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. D...

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In...

Prisoners dilemma or stag hunt

Over Christmas I had chance to read The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure by Brian Skyrms. A nice read, very interesting and thought provoking. There’s a couple of things in the book that prompt further discussion. The one I want to focus on in this post is the distinction between the stag hunt game and the prisoners dilemma game.    To be sure what we are talking about, here is a specific version of both type of game. Adam and Eve independently need to decide whether to cooperate or defect. The payoff matrix details their payoff for any combination of choices, where the first number is the payoff of Adam and the second number the payoff of Eve. For example, in the Prisoners Dilemma, if Adam cooperates and Eve defects then Adam gets 65 and Eve gets 165. Prisoners Dilemma Eve Cooperate Defect Adam Cooperate 140, 140 65, 165 Defect 165,...