Skip to main content

Breastfeeding, externalities and the Coase Theorem

Saturday morning I heard a somewhat intense debate on the radio about whether a mother should breast-feed in public. The debate was sparked by an incident in a restaurant where a breast-feeding mother was asked to 'use a blanket'. Views were completely polarized. Some, like me, thought it outrageous to criticize someone for breast-feeding in public. Others, thought it outrageous to breast-feed in public! This polarization of views is a perfect illustration of the reciprocal nature of externalities, first pointed out by Ronald Coase.
        The 'textbook' picture of an externality is typically one of good and evil, like a factory polluting the water that local people drink. The clear suggestion is that the evil doer, the factory in this case, should take account of the effect they have on others. Often, however, externalities do not lend themselves to a simple good and evil. That's the case in the breast-feeding example: Some would place the breast-feeding mother in the role of evil and others would place the person complaining about breast-feeding in the role of evil.
        Given that the breast-feeding example has no clear distinction between good and evil the reciprocal nature of externalities is simpler to appreciate. In particular, a woman's breast-feeding in public creates a negative externality for those who do not want to watch someone breast-feeding. But, banning breast-feeding in public creates a negative externality for any mother forced to feed her baby in the wash-room. To stop a negative externality inevitably creates a different kind of negative externality. And note that this holds even if we have a clear distinction between good or evil. To ban water pollution, for example, imposes a negative externality on the factory.
         An appreciation of the reciprocal nature of externalities led to Coase's celebrated theorem on how to increase efficiency in the presence of externalities. The theory essentially says that if there are clearly defined property rights (and negotiation costs are negligible) interested parties will negotiate towards an efficient outcome no matter who owns the property rights. For example, if local people have the property right they could charge the factory for its pollution. While, if the factory has the property right it could be paid by local people to reduce pollution. Similarly, if the person who does not like to see breast-feeding has the property right she could charge someone for breast-feeding. While if the person who breast-feeds has the property right she could be paid to breast-feed in the wash-room. These charges or payments correct incentives and 'eliminate' the externality.
          Well, that is the theory. In practice, I think the breast-feeding example points to a fundamental floor in the application of the Coase Theorem. We know that people dislike 'unfair' outcomes. And that they would rather 'suffer' than accept an unfair outcome. This suggests that someone may be unwilling to negotiate towards an efficient outcome unless they believe that they are in the position of evil. Consider, for instance, the factory example: The idea that the factory would compensate local people for pollution seems entirely reasonable. The idea that local people would pay the factory to reduce pollution clangs with common sense. And what about the breast-feeding example: If the breast-feeding mother believes it is her basic right to breast-feed in public she is not going to want to pay to breast-feed. And if the person who does not like to see breast-feeding believes it is her basic right to not see breast-feeding she is not going to want to compensate someone for not breast-feeding.
          The basic point here is that an assignment of property rights does not change beliefs. British law clearly gives the property right to the breast-feeding mother, but that does not change the beliefs of the person who does not want to see breast-feeding. In a similar way, British law clearly gives the property right to people who do not smoke cigarettes, but that does not change the beliefs of the those who think they have the right to smoke. The Coase Theorem may, therefore, be of somewhat limited applicability. So, while it is important for governments to assign property rights for distributional reasons, as in the breast-feeding case, do not expect to see the most efficient outcome as a consequence.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Revealed preference, WARP, SARP and GARP

The basic idea behind revealed preference is incredibly simple: we try to infer something useful about a person's preferences by observing the choices they make. The topic, however, confuses many a student and academic alike, particularly when we get on to WARP, SARP and GARP. So, let us see if we can make some sense of it all.           In trying to explain revealed preference I want to draw on a  study  by James Andreoni and John Miller published in Econometrica . They look at people's willingness to share money with another person. Specifically subjects were given questions like:  Q1. Divide 60 tokens: Hold _____ at $1 each and Pass _____ at $1 each.  In this case there were 60 tokens to split and each token was worth $1. So, for example, if they held 40 tokens and passed 20 then they would get $40 and the other person $20. Consider another question: Q2. D...

Nash bargaining solution

Following the tragic death of John Nash in May I thought it would be good to explain some of his main contributions to game theory. Where better to start than the Nash bargaining solution. This is surely one of the most beautiful results in game theory and was completely unprecedented. All the more remarkable that Nash came up with the idea at the start of his graduate studies!          The Nash solution is a 'solution' to a two-person bargaining problem . To illustrate, suppose we have Adam and Beth bargaining over how to split some surplus. If they fail to reach agreement they get payoffs €a and €b respectively. The pair (a, b) is called the disagreement point . If they agree then they can achieve any pair of payoffs within some set F of feasible payoff points . I'll give some examples later. For the problem to be interesting we need there to be some point (A, B) in F such that A > a and B > b. In...

Prisoners dilemma or stag hunt

Over Christmas I had chance to read The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure by Brian Skyrms. A nice read, very interesting and thought provoking. There’s a couple of things in the book that prompt further discussion. The one I want to focus on in this post is the distinction between the stag hunt game and the prisoners dilemma game.    To be sure what we are talking about, here is a specific version of both type of game. Adam and Eve independently need to decide whether to cooperate or defect. The payoff matrix details their payoff for any combination of choices, where the first number is the payoff of Adam and the second number the payoff of Eve. For example, in the Prisoners Dilemma, if Adam cooperates and Eve defects then Adam gets 65 and Eve gets 165. Prisoners Dilemma Eve Cooperate Defect Adam Cooperate 140, 140 65, 165 Defect 165,...